Produced by Charles Wells Revised 2017-02-25 Introduction to this website website TOC website index blog Back to head of sets chapter
The following notation for sets of numbers is fairly standard.
Until the 1930's, Germany was the world center for scientific and mathematical study, and at least until the 1960's, being able to read scientific German was required of anyone who wanted a degree in science. Now, some German universities teach some high-level courses in English.
Let $a$ and $b$ be real numbers.
The notation $\left( a,b \right)$ is also used to mean the ordered pair with first coordinate $a$ and second coordinate $b$.
You can picture the set of real numbers as a line infinitely long in both directions. Numbers $a$ and $b$ may be pictured as points on the line, this way:
The open interval $\left( a,b \right)$ is the set of points between $a$ and $b$, not including $a$ and $b$. The closed interval $\left[ a,b \right]$ is the set of points between $a$ and $b$, including $a$ and $b$.
The empty set is the unique set with no elements at all. It is denoted by “$\varnothing$” or sometimes by "$\{\,\}$". (See Usage of the symbol $\varnothing$.)
The existence and uniqueness of the empty set follows directly from the specification for sets: The empty set is completely determined by the fact that it has no elements.
Since the empty set is a set, it can be an element of another set
Consider this: although "$\varnothing$" and "$\{\, \}$" both denote the empty set, $\left\{ \varnothing \right\}$ is not the empty set; it is the set whose only element is the empty set. The set $\left\{ \varnothing \right\}$ is in fact a singleton set.
The set of subsets of the two-element set $\{1,2\}$ is the set \[\{\varnothing,\{1\},\{2\},\{1,2\}\}\]
Because there is only one empty set, $\left\{ x\in \mathrm{\mathbb{R}}\,|\,{{x}^{2}}\lt 0 \right\}$, $[3, 2]$ and $(3, 2)$ are all exactly the same set. The two statements below say this in two different ways. I recommend that you think about them until you understand that they are really saying the same thing.
The empty set does not get along very well with the way you think about bunches of things. The following examples give useful illustrations of how a math idea (empty set in this case) may not fit your intuition.
If you think of a set as a container, the empty set is simply an empty container. The only problem with this is that there is only one empty set, whereas normally you expect that any number of different containers can be empty.
If you think of a set as a collection, there is a problem: If I didn’t own any chess pieces, I would not talk about “my collection of chess pieces”. If you don’t have something, you don’t have a collection of them!
The concept of collection also has the same problem that “container” has: You would mean two different things by the statements
But there is only one empty set. It does not come in types!
If you think of a set as a pointer to its elements, then the empty set is the same as the null pointer. Again there is a problem: A computer program can have many different pointers set to null at the same time. But there is only one empty set.
As always, images and metaphors for the concept of set produce cognitive dissonance. Remember:
The definition always overrides your intuition
It would be perfectly possible to use a set theory with more than one empty set; for example, to agree that the empty set of integers is different from the empty set of continuous functions. In effect, that is what happens in certain versions of type theory. But the only-one-empty-set point of view is essentially standard in most math texts.
A set containing exactly one element is called a singleton set.
Because a set is distinct from its elements, a set with exactly one element is not the same thing as the element. Thus $\{3\}$ is a set, not a number, whereas $3$ is a number, not a set.
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 2.5 License.